It never ceases to amaze me how many on the left fashion themselves "progressives" who are on the cutting edge of political innovation and insight. The left's main ideas, equality and unity, have been around for thousands of years. Every time a political community actually attempts to implement these ideas, economic hardship and eventually ruin are visited upon them.
One of the earliest and most eloquent debunkers of the ideals of socialism was Aristotle, who criticized the proto-socialist Phaleas and the Western European philosopher of the "enlightened police state" Plato. Far from being outdated and esoteric, much of what Aristotle addresses in The Politics speaks directly to many of the assumptions of the political left in America today.
Book Two, Part I
Our purpose is to consider what form of political community is best of all for those who are most able to realize their ideal of life. We must therefore examine not only this but other constitutions, both such as actually exist in well-governed states, and any theoretical forms which are held in esteem; that what is good and useful may be brought to light. And let no one suppose that in seeking for something beyond them we are anxious to make a sophistical display at any cost; we only undertake this inquiry because all the constitutions with which we are acquainted are faulty.
We will begin with the natural beginning of the subject. Three alternatives are conceivable: The members of a state must either have (1) all things or (2) nothing in common, or (3) some things in common and some not. That they should have nothing in common is clearly impossible, for the constitution is a community, and must at any rate have a common place- one city will be in one place, and the citizens are those who share in that one city. But should a well ordered state have all things, as far as may be, in common, or some only and not others? For the citizens might conceivably have wives and children and property in common, as Socrates proposes in the Republic of Plato. Which is better, our present condition, or the proposed new order of society.
Book Two, Part III
But, even supposing that it were best for the community to have the greatest degree of unity, this unity is by no means proved to follow from the fact 'of all men saying "mine" and "not mine" at the same instant of time,' which, according to Socrates, is the sign of perfect unity in a state. For the word 'all' is ambiguous. If the meaning be that every individual says 'mine' and 'not mine' at the same time, then perhaps the result at which Socrates aims may be in some degree accomplished; each man will call the same person his own son and the same person his wife, and so of his property and of all that falls to his lot. This, however, is not the way in which people would speak who had their had their wives and children in common; they would say 'all' but not 'each.' In like manner their property would be described as belonging to them, not severally but collectively. There is an obvious fallacy in the term 'all': like some other words, 'both,' 'odd,' 'even,' it is ambiguous, and even in abstract argument becomes a source of logical puzzles. That all persons call the same thing mine in the sense in which each does so may be a fine thing, but it is impracticable; or if the words are taken in the other sense, such a unity in no way conduces to harmony.
And there is another objection to the proposal. For that which is common to the greatest number has the least care bestowed upon it [also known as "The Tragedy of the Commons" - ed.]. Every one thinks chiefly of his own, hardly at all of the common interest; and only when he is himself concerned as an individual. For besides other considerations, everybody is more inclined to neglect the duty which he expects another to fulfill ; as in families many attendants are often less useful than a few. Each citizen will have a thousand sons who will not be his sons individually but anybody will be equally the son of anybody, and will therefore be neglected by all alike.
Further, upon this principle, every one will use the word 'mine' of one who is prospering or the reverse, however small a fraction he may himself be of the whole number; the same boy will be 'so and so's son,' the son of each of the thousand, or whatever be the number of the citizens; and even about this he will not be positive; for it is impossible to know who chanced to have a child, or whether, if one came into existence, it has survived [see Plato's Republic - ed.]. But which is better- for each to say 'mine' in this way, making a man the same relation to two thousand or ten thousand citizens, or to use the word 'mine' in the ordinary and more restricted sense? For usually the same person is called by one man his own son whom another calls his own brother or cousin or kinsman- blood relation or connection by marriage either of himself or of some relation of his, and yet another his clansman or tribesman; and how much better is it to be the real cousin of somebody than to be a son after Plato's fashion! [...]
Book Two, Part V
Next let us consider what should be our arrangements about property: should the citizens of the perfect state have their possessions in common or not? This question may be discussed separately from the enactments about women and children. Even supposing that the women and children belong to individuals, according to the custom which is at present universal, may there not be an advantage in having and using possessions in common? Three cases are possible: (1) the soil may be appropriated, but the produce may be thrown for consumption into the common stock; and this is the practice of some nations. Or (2), the soil may be common, and may be cultivated in common, but the produce divided among individuals for their private use; this is a form of common property which is said to exist among certain barbarians. Or (3), the soil and the produce may be alike common.
When the husbandmen are not the owners, the case will be different and easier to deal with; but when they till the ground for themselves the question of ownership will give a world of trouble. If they do not share equally enjoyments and toils, those who labor much and get little will necessarily complain of those who labor little and receive or consume much. But indeed there is always a difficulty in men living together and having all human relations in common, but especially in their having common property. The partnerships of fellow-travelers are an example to the point; for they generally fall out over everyday matters and quarrel about any trifle which turns up. So with servants: we are most able to take offense at those with whom we most we most frequently come into contact in daily life.
These are only some of the disadvantages which attend the community of property; the present arrangement, if improved as it might be by good customs and laws, would be far better, and would have the advantages of both systems. Property should be in a certain sense common, but, as a general rule, private; for, when everyone has a distinct interest, men will not complain of one another, and they will make more progress, because every one will be attending to his own business. And yet by reason of goodness, and in respect of use, 'Friends,' as the proverb says, 'will have all things common.' Even now there are traces of such a principle, showing that it is not impracticable, but, in well-ordered states, exists already to a certain extent and may be carried further. For, although every man has his own property, some things he will place at the disposal of his friends,while of others he shares the use with them. The Lacedaemonians, for example, use one another's slaves, and horses, and dogs, as if they were their own; and when they lack provisions on a journey, they appropriate what they find in the fields throughout the country. It is clearly better that property should be private, but the use of it common; and the special business of the legislator is to create in men this benevolent disposition.
Again, how immeasurably greater is the pleasure, when a man feels a thing to be his own; for surely the love of self is a feeling implanted by nature and not given in vain, although selfishness is rightly censured; this, however, is not the mere love of self, but the love of self in excess, like the miser's love of money; for all, or almost all, men love money and other such objects in a measure [Obviously, Aristotle and Ayn Rand differ on the "virtue of selfishness." - ed.].
And further, there is the greatest pleasure in doing a kindness or service to friends or guests or companions, which can only be rendered when a man has private property. These advantages are lost by excessive unification of the state. The exhibition of two virtues, besides, is visibly annihilated in such a state: first, temperance towards women (for it is an honorable action to abstain from another's wife for temperance' sake); secondly, liberality in the matter of property. No one, when men have all things in common, will any longer set an example of liberality or do any liberal action; for liberality consists in the use which is made of property.
Such legislation may have a specious appearance of benevolence; men readily listen to it, and are easily induced to believe that in some wonderful manner everybody will become everybody's friend, especially when some one is heard denouncing the evils now existing in states, suits about contracts, convictions for perjury, flatteries of rich men and the like, which are said to arise out of the possession of private property. These evils, however, are due to a very different cause- the wickedness of human nature. Indeed, we see that there is much more quarrelling among those who have all things in common, though there are not many of them when compared with the vast numbers who have private property.
Again, we ought to reckon, not only the evils from which the citizens will be saved, but also the advantages which they will lose. The life which they are to lead appears to be quite impracticable. The error of Socrates must be attributed to the false notion of unity from which he starts. Unity there should be, both of the family and of the state, but in some respects only. For there is a point at which a state may attain such a degree of unity as to be no longer a state, or at which, without actually ceasing to exist, it will become an inferior state, like harmony passing into unison, or rhythm which has been reduced to a single foot. [...]
Book Two, Part VII
Moreover, civil troubles arise, not only out of the inequality of property, but out of the inequality of honor, though in opposite ways. For the common people quarrel about the inequality of property, the higher class about the equality of honor; as the poet says,
"The bad and good alike in honor share. "
There are crimes of which the motive is want; and for these Phaleas [a forerunner of Marx by about two thousand years - ed.] expects to find a cure in the equalization of property, which will take away from a man the temptation to be a highwayman, because he is hungry or cold. But want is not the sole incentive to crime; men also wish to enjoy themselves and not to be in a state of desire- they wish to cure some desire, going beyond the necessities of life, which preys upon them; nay, this is not the only reason- they may desire superfluities in order to enjoy pleasures unaccompanied with pain, and therefore they commit crimes.
Now what is the cure of these three disorders? Of the first, moderate possessions and occupation; of the second, habits of temperance; as to the third, if any desire pleasures which depend on themselves, they will find the satisfaction of their desires nowhere but in philosophy; for all other pleasures we are dependent on others. The fact is that the greatest crimes are caused by excess and not by necessity. Men do not become tyrants in order that they may not suffer cold; and hence great is the honor bestowed, not on him who kills a thief, but on him who kills a tyrant. [...]
The equalization of property is one of the things that tend to prevent the citizens from quarrelling. Not that the gain in this direction is very great. For the nobles will be dissatisfied because they think themselves worthy of more than an equal share of honors; and this is often found to be a cause of sedition and revolution. And the avarice of mankind is insatiable; at one time two obols was pay enough; but now, when this sum has become customary, men always want more and more without end; for it is of the nature of desire not to be satisfied, and most men live only for the gratification of it. [End.]
Aristotle continues by preaching virtue and temperance rather than redistribution of wealth and equalization of property. Nearly two thousand years later, an economic system would harness greed for the benefit of mankind; this is a moral conundrum that has baffled and disgusted the left for over two hundred years.
But much fault in the left's understanding of capitalism lay in their definition of greed. Is greed developing a product that people want to buy and putting men and women to work to produce it? And can many people buy mass produced goods if the majority live on subsistence wages, as Marx argued would inevitably happen in a "capitalist" system? Does greed actually benefit society when there is a sound linkage between production and perceived utility?
There are some serious root philosophical problems that go unchallenged on the left; and indeed that was the reason for the marxist left's turn to neo-marxism, with Gramsci, Alinsky, and the Frankfurt School. The left's shift to cultural marxism belied that their understanding of reality, as expressed by Marx's dialectical materialism, was weak.
This is why the left must attack, smear, lie, and slander. The left's ideals rest on feet of clay, as we can see with Obama's naive pronouncements, which are debunked at every turn.
The left has lied for so long to justify their own power to "transform" the world - namely, by obliterating every institution lending the United States (and many Western European nations) strength and stability - that they have come to believe their own lies. This is why the left cannot have an honest conversation. That is why the left must cheat.
Because to the left, it is not about being right anymore, it is just about being in control. The problem is, what they want to control is beyond their control. So their best intentions must inevitably lead them, and those in their charge, down a path of increasing authoritarianism.
5 comments:
Being a leftist is a religion. It's that simple. Facts don't matter and either does integrity. The ends justify the means for them. I know Orthodox Jews and Born-Again Christians and most of them are infinitely more open-minded than leftists. Unfortunately, the left has managed to indoctrinate young people with their public schools and the MSM are part of this religion so they are just as uneducated and braiwashed.
Thank you for posting this and all of your other very educative essays. I thank you and Reaganx for the education!
Hey, it's fun having someone to share discoveries with. Thanks for following along, Nora.
Yes thanks for going along Nora; without you, it would be a lonely world for Reasonjester.
Dear Miss Anonymous,
So sad. You are always ready with a comment that has nothing to do with the issues at hand. You think like a toddler. I used to be on the left and I thought the same way and was always surrounded by same. Grow up. Try to think deeper than 'Yes, we can' and 'Teach Peace' and the other superficial BS that means nothing.
Hey I have three Internet friends here (minus you) - but fifty three follow my musings on the Federalist Papers, ten follow me on Dennis Miller Zone (including Dennis from time to time), five follow me on Mark Levin Fan Forum, three follow me on Ann Coulter - take that out to six degrees of separation and I influence the world baby!!!
Post a Comment